Thursday, October 24, 2019
Philosophy â⬠Conscience (90/90) Essay
Discuss critically the view that we should always follow our conscience when making ethical decisions It has traditionally been proposed that the conscience is an established body of authority, essentially justifying the view that it should be ââ¬Ëfollowedââ¬â¢. Many notable figures throughout history ââ¬â Aquinas, Butler, Plato, Freud ââ¬â have structurally placed it in a potent rà ¯Ã ¿Ã ½le. Whether this is by means of tripartite analogies, hierarchical standing or even religious eminence, the conscience serves a theoretical, and indeed practical, function as the human and societal arbiter. But then, there is also a possible disparity between the states of individual and collective conscience, contributing to the difficulties in determining which conscience is more suited to enacting ââ¬Ëethical decisionsââ¬â¢. This predicates an interesting dichotomy: the conscience either does not maintain this degree of control or, conversely, the conscienceââ¬â¢s increased social standing grants it an even greater level of authority. It can similarly be questioned whet her or not the conscienceââ¬â¢s proposed supremacy necessitates an individualââ¬â¢s reliance on it, or even, whether it is needed at all. Ideas in connection with the conscience are far-reaching. The notion of ââ¬Ëethical decisionsââ¬â¢ being governed by the conscience implies that there is a principal rà ¯Ã ¿Ã ½le the conscience must play in enacting them. But, as addressed above, there are solid questions over its reliability: its seemingly potent position and even its existence. My argument follows an objective line, paying close attention to that factor in which man is of sole importance. The human being is the entity the conscience must work alongside, and vice versa. There is a clear discrepancy between common definitions of ââ¬Ëconsciousnessââ¬â¢, in turn emphasising the inconsistency of thought on the matter. The Collins Dictionary, for example, defines ââ¬Ëconsciousnessââ¬â¢ as being ââ¬Å"aware of oneââ¬â¢s surroundingsâ⬠1; in contrast with the Concise Oxford Dictionary which classifies it as being ââ¬Å"aware of and responding to oneââ¬â¢s surroundingsâ⬠2. Herein, at the outset, lies an issue. ââ¬ËSurroundingsââ¬â¢ and conditions are clearly noted by both definitions, yet the human acknowledgement and ââ¬Ëresponseââ¬â¢ to them are not so. This irregularity is highly relevant when trying to determine the conscienceââ¬â¢s rà ¯Ã ¿Ã ½le in the individualââ¬â¢s ââ¬Ëdecisionââ¬â¢-making. The mindââ¬â¢s influence on the individual, the individualââ¬â¢s place in society, and, indeed, individuals themselves, are key to this matter. ***************** ââ¬Å"May God himself, the God of peace, sanctify you through and through. May your whole spirit, soul and body be kept blameless at the coming of our Lord Jesus Christâ⬠3 Presented above is the Biblical proposition most considered to be supportive of the tripartite theory of the Godhead. Theologically, ââ¬Ëthreeââ¬â¢ has been a consistent Biblical presence, ââ¬Å"It should be noted at the outset that the Biblical authorsââ¬â¢ use of the number three is abundantly attestedâ⬠4 ââ¬â The Holy Trinity, Noahââ¬â¢s three sons and Jobââ¬â¢s three daughters being notable cases of this. Accordingly, the human being consists of ââ¬Ëthreeââ¬â¢ separate elements; either ââ¬Ëbodyââ¬â¢, ââ¬Ësoulââ¬â¢ and ââ¬Ëspiritââ¬â¢, as is noted above, or, most applicable to the question of conscience: i) appetites ii) affections, and iii) reason ââ¬â the latter having familiar associations with the conscience. But where does this come into the idea of ââ¬Ëfollowingââ¬â¢ oneââ¬â¢s conscience? Simply put, it is the idea that the conscience is dominant in its essence; that theologians, philosophers and psychologists throughout times past have placed it above appetites and affections. Noted examples of this are Aquinasââ¬â¢ ââ¬ËHierarchy of Beingââ¬â¢, Platoââ¬â¢s ââ¬ËAllegory of the Chariotââ¬â¢, Freudââ¬â¢s idea of the id, ego and superego, and others; all leading to one literally presented conclusion ââ¬â conscience is ââ¬Ëbossââ¬â¢, and ergo, should be ââ¬Ëfollowedââ¬â¢. Thomistic philosophy places the conscience in a divine rank; alongside the Bible, the Church and Mankind as a whole. It is divine and institutional law; guided through human mechanisms by the Synderesis Rule: ââ¬Å"the innate principle in the moral consciousness of every person which directs the agent to good and restrains him from evilâ⬠5. This can be seen to relate directly to the idea of a benevolent conscience making ââ¬Ëethical decisionsââ¬â¢ ââ¬â ââ¬Ëgoodââ¬â¢ being the ultimate goal. Butler takes a similar position ââ¬â ââ¬Å"man is born to virtueâ⬠6 ââ¬â ââ¬Ëself loveââ¬â¢ and ââ¬Ëbenevolenceââ¬â¢ being the individualââ¬â¢s guide. But, one might ask whether the apparent requirement to do ââ¬Ëgoodââ¬â¢ is really an objective balance. Can one really make an ââ¬Ëethical decisionââ¬â¢ without knowing the evil? 7 Aquinas asserted five primary precepts which the conscience formulates in an ââ¬Ëethicalââ¬â¢ judgement ââ¬â self preservation and preservation of the innocent, continuation of the species, education of children, living in a society and worshipping God. Despite the need for these to be followed, and, of course, definitive of how we make ââ¬Ëethical decisionsââ¬â¢, it is the fifth that one finds enticing for this particular study. ââ¬ËWorshipping Godââ¬â¢, the church ââ¬â a state of authority ââ¬â or, indeed, perceived authority, guiding our actions. It conforms to the hierarchy of being (an apt link with the tripartite theory) and is a premise for Godââ¬â¢s ââ¬Ëbenign tyrannyââ¬â¢. God is the pure form of Reason, and is so at the top of the hierarchy, subordinated by mankind ââ¬â affections ââ¬â and animals ââ¬â pure appetite. By this we can see that this hierarchical method is multi-levelled ââ¬â the human being comprises these attributes just as a collective hierarchy does. They are simply metaphors for the conscienceââ¬â¢s divine authority on a bodily and societal level. This is further supported by Platoââ¬â¢s ââ¬ËAllegory of the Chariotââ¬â¢; the charioteer representing Intellect/Reason/Conscience, the white horse signifying the aforementioned morals and affections, and the black horse symbolising appetites. One might be too facetious in making this interpretation but the use of a horse somewhat indicates that human beings are majorly of beastly appetites, other than reason ââ¬â are we Godââ¬â¢s ââ¬Ëbeastsââ¬â¢ as it were? Plato himself judged that: ââ¬Å"manâ⬠¦is a tame or civilized animal; nevertheless, he requires proper instruction and a fortunate nature, and then of all animals he becomes the most divine and most civilized; but if he be insufficiently or ill-educated he is the most savage of earthly creatures.â⬠8 Yet, he conversely gives the analogous horse human traits: ââ¬Å"he is a lover of honour and modesty and temperance, and the follower of true glory; he needs no touch of the whip, but is guided by word and admonition only.â⬠9 Even more interesting is Platoââ¬â¢s use of a human being in Godââ¬â¢s rà ¯Ã ¿Ã ½le. This gives two ideas; God is either being anthropomorphised (putting him in inferior standing) or, alternatively, human conscience is God-ly10 ââ¬â maybe God is our conscience. Maybe He is mankind. Newman supports the former idea; ââ¬Å"an echo implies a voice; a voice, a speaker. That speaker I love and revereâ⬠11, by the literal hearing of voices. The ââ¬Ëspeakerââ¬â¢ is the indwelling voice ââ¬â the conscience ââ¬â and the reverberation of Godââ¬â¢s direct message. Here, on the surface, we can clearly see, due to the divine cloud hanging over this matter (ââ¬ËGod is goodââ¬â¢), that the conscience should be ââ¬Ëfollowedââ¬â¢ when making ââ¬Ëethical decisionsââ¬â¢. Yet, one might ask the fundamental question of whether the conscience is worthy of its place above appetites and affections. The empiricist, David Hume, makes his opinion on the matter quite clear: ââ¬Å"reason is, and ought only to be the slave of the passions, and can never pretend to any other office than to serve and obey themâ⬠12. He provides a clear argument against ââ¬Ëalwaysââ¬â¢ ââ¬Ëfollowingââ¬â¢ our conscience when making ââ¬Ëethical decisionsââ¬â¢, in favour of our appetites. One might take the view that our primitive nature, without the influence of our conscience and an interventionist (or determinant) society is more equipped to make ââ¬Ëethical decisionsââ¬â¢. Indeed, the Reformation encouraged the break-away from the Church of Rome and set the individual conscience, not ecclesiastical authority, at the centre of religious life. As will be addressed in further detail later, if our conscience is distorted by society the individual may not be in full control of his own ââ¬Ëethical decisionsââ¬â¢. One could conversely argue, however, that, as Plato seemingly hinted at above, Hume degrades humanity to the level of animals; that we have no power to reason and therefore cannot achieve ââ¬ËGod-linessââ¬â¢ or make ââ¬Ëethical decisionsââ¬â¢ at all. Plato supplemented the ideas purveyed by his ââ¬ËAllegory of the Chariotââ¬â¢ through another work The Republic, which, for this essay, provides the basis for examination of the relationship between individual and societal conscience. As with Aquinas, it is a question of hierarchy. The workers ââ¬â appetite followers ââ¬â and the soldiers ââ¬â protectors of the state and morals ââ¬â are both subservient to the philosopher-kings ââ¬â the embodiment of reason. Platoââ¬â¢s view was that of an elitist society with the core conscience in charge; ââ¬Å"knowledge is powerâ⬠13 (ââ¬Å"Conscience is kingâ⬠14) or, as I might conversely argue, ââ¬Ëpower is knowledgeââ¬â¢ (ââ¬ËKing is conscienceââ¬â¢). One can draw parallels with Orwellââ¬â¢s dystopian novel Nineteen Eighty-Four, which, for me, offers an even more appropriate portrayal of this idea: the lowly ââ¬Ëprolesââ¬â¢ comprising the vast majority of society ââ¬â governed by appetites ââ¬â the Outer Party ââ¬â controlled by state values and propaganda, morals, affections ââ¬â and the Inner Party and Big Brother, the core of the state; the quintessence of the conscience, ââ¬Å"it is impossible to see reality except by looking through the eyes of the Partyâ⬠15. These two examples demonstrate the conscience of the individual being mirrored in society. It raises issues as to whether the conscience of the collective should be ââ¬Ëfollowedââ¬â¢ when making ââ¬Ëethical decisionsââ¬â¢ as opposed to that of the limited individual; ââ¬Å"only in the mind of the party, which is collective and immortalâ⬠16 ââ¬â drawing distinctly Marxist parallels, and, perhaps more relevantly, conforming to the Thomistic precept of ââ¬Ëliving in a societyââ¬â¢. One can link this to the thoughts of Soloveychik; that ââ¬Å"conscience canââ¬â¢t be someoneââ¬â¢s own. Conscience is both personal and universalâ⬠17. The pluralism, ââ¬Ëweââ¬â¢, established in the initial proposition is markedly addressed with these connections to societal conscience. One extremity that may arise from this elitist, authoritarian ideal, however, is the issue of mind-control (ââ¬Å"Big Brother Is Watching Youâ⬠). A conscientious hierarchical society controlling the psyche of the masses may fulfil the rà ¯Ã ¿Ã ½le of the individual in a more oblique, inflated manner. Appetites, affection and reason being governed by class structure; bringing about a socially solidified conscience. One might apply this to F.H. Bradleyââ¬â¢s personification: ââ¬Å"our function [is] as an organâ⬠in a ââ¬Å"social organismâ⬠. Thus, if conscience is uniform among individuals, why might ââ¬Ëethical decisionsââ¬â¢ not be carried out similarly? Baruch Spinoza believed that Godââ¬â¢s knowledge is distilled through humanity: ââ¬Å"an idea is adequate and perfect insofar as it represents knowledge of the eternal and infinite essence of Godâ⬠18. Giving further substance to the idea of an individualââ¬â¢s morals (their ââ¬Ëethicalââ¬â¢ make-up) being reflected on a collective level. Hume, however, argues against this, ââ¬Å"nothing is more surprising than the easiness with which the many are governed by the fewâ⬠19, pondering the dominance of a reasoned minority ââ¬â the collectiveââ¬â¢s core conscience ââ¬â in turn eradicating the starting point for this theory. An answer to the issue in the proposition, however, is still not possible at this point. One cannot yet determine whether the conscience should be ââ¬Ëfollowedââ¬â¢ when making ââ¬Ëethical decisionsââ¬â¢ because of the sheer amount of subjectivity over the ethics of elitism. Still, the plausibility of a societal conscience maintaining this degree of authority is questionable. Despite the seemingly loose connections mentioned above, the conscience of the collective is undoubtedly dissimilar to that of the individual. The juxtaposed issues of freedom and conflicting individual mentality are enough in themselves to maintain this viewpoint. Obviously, this makes us question whether making references to literal states of authority is actually worthwhile. The individual has a conscience which both conflicts and complements the state/collective consciousness. Linking to the above issue, are governments/collectives always an objective balance? Seemingly, there are corrupt governments; history has shown there to be corruption in the Church and other elements of society that control the individualââ¬â¢s mindset. Yet it is indubitably the case that the mind (and conscience) is always influenced by the society in which it operates. This presents a mind-blowing paradox. Society is not only determined by a central conscience but the conscience of the individual is conversely determined by society. This might then suggest that whatever the case, the sole function that drives societal conditions, indirectly assumes its authority over the individual. J.B Watson ââ¬â the ââ¬ËFather of Behaviourismââ¬â¢ ââ¬â proposed: ââ¬Å"give me a dozen healthy infants, well-formed, and my own specified world to bring them up in and Iââ¬â¢ll guarantee to take any one at random and train him to become any type of specialist I might selectâ⬠20 He places himself ââ¬â a core being with societal influence ââ¬â in an authoritative position over specified individuals. This can be compared with the Freudian idea that the superego develops throughout childhood by external influences. The human being is born with the id; the basis for appetites, eros (sex) and thanatos (death) drives ââ¬â these drives could interestingly be seen in a belligerently potent rà ¯Ã ¿Ã ½le, supporting the idea of appetital authority à ¯Ã ¿Ã ½ la Hume. Subsequently, the ego develops; the presentable faà ¯Ã ¿Ã ½ade that we apply to the world; our affections. Then the superego, our reason and conscience; the irrefutable censor of the human mind. It develops throughout childhood. In tandem with the environmental development, or determinism, mentioned above, ââ¬Å"children are completely egoistic; they feel their needs intensely and strive ruthlessly to satisfy themâ⬠21. So by this then, we can see that the tripartite, ââ¬Ëthreeââ¬â¢; is a consistent literal basis for the presentation of the conscience. I would, however, question whether this is a valuable method by which to present its authority. There are obvious differences between the theories presented by each of these figures; Freud ââ¬â socio-psychological; Aquinas ââ¬â religious; Plato ââ¬â the soul. These differences mean something. For one, each has specific rà ¯Ã ¿Ã ½les. Some may apply strictly to societal conscience (Platoââ¬â¢s Republic and Orwellââ¬â¢s Nineteen Eighty-Four), others may apply merely to the individual (Freud and Platoââ¬â¢s ââ¬ËAllegory of the Chariotââ¬â¢). It is nonetheless interesting that the tripartite is consistent throughout different periods and cultures. Ultimately, it comes to the point where one must consult Freudââ¬â¢s verdict to prove what these give us, ââ¬Å"analogies, it is true, decide nothing, but they can make on e feel more at homeâ⬠22. How else, then, can the conscience be interpreted authoritatively and conclusive of how we make ââ¬Ëethical decisionsââ¬â¢? Put simply, the conscience is an alarm: it is disturbing; it forces the individual to put themselves in uncomfortable situations and concurrently feel the effects of these. Although there are religious sides to this, for example, the threat, ââ¬Å"he who acts against his conscience loses his soulâ⬠23, the principal factor here is indeed guilt. Of course, guilt is the one thing that the layman will consider alongside the conscience. Conscience is guilt to many. The objective conscience works by putting the individual at a discomfort, Freud believing that guilt is the consequence of not obeying it. Dostoyevsky provides a fine example of this in his notorious work Crime and Punishment, where the protagonist, Rodion Raskolnikov, experiences continual mental anguish following his homicidal actions. The novel gives the idea of mental demons ââ¬â ââ¬Å"If he has a conscience he will suffer for his mistake. That will be punishment as well as the prison.â⬠24 Rodionââ¬â¢s shame ultimately forces him to confess. He ââ¬Ëfollowsââ¬â¢ his guilty conscience to make an ââ¬Ëethical decisionââ¬â¢. This issue is also given great attention in Shakespeareââ¬â¢s tragedy, Hamlet, in which the king, Claudius, comes to realise, in retrospect, the implications of his fratricide; ââ¬Å"my stronger guilt defeats my strong intentâ⬠25. He is, however, prone to continuing his murderous tendencies. Although this is a literary construction, one might suggest that Claudius reverts to his thanatos drive, the superego not taking precedence. Another interpretation is that he adheres to the belief that you ââ¬Å"perform a sin twice and it will cease to be a crimeâ⬠26, providing a distinctly self-centred stance. Above all, however, this notion of guilt leads us to question whether the conscienceââ¬â¢s precedence actually does entail our reliance on it. If the conscience can be seen to be malicious one might assume it is not all good or a worthy mechanism by which to make ââ¬Ëethical decisionsââ¬â¢. Should we ââ¬Ëalwaysââ¬â¢ ââ¬Ëfollowââ¬â¢ our conscience if it occasionally encourages us to impart malevolence towards others? Yet, admittedly, I have placed the conscience, somewhat clumsily, in a potent rà ¯Ã ¿Ã ½le by inappropriately treating it as an inanimate transcendent ââ¬Ëobjectââ¬â¢. ââ¬ËThe conscienceââ¬â¢ is a misleading phrase ââ¬â it can not be addressed in literal terms as the above-mentioned figures and I have done so. It is an ambiguous concept; a culmination of ideas, not a figurehead or core being that people must obey. In doing this I have partially neglected the fundamental points initially outlined; those of human response to the conscience, as well as the issue of ââ¬Ëethical decisionsââ¬â¢. The point is that the human being is its conscience ââ¬â they work in tandem ââ¬â yet the individual conscience is contingent on the social conscience and vice versa. It is an eternal cog of human reasoning, working jointly to maintain relations and prevent wrongdoing. There is a deterministic problem associated with this question: if the conscience is a necessary mechanism then seemingly we cannot escape it ââ¬â ââ¬Ëalwaysââ¬â¢ following our conscience places it in a more authoritative rà ¯Ã ¿Ã ½le than a judicial one. Aquinas, for one, believed that ââ¬Ëfollowingââ¬â¢ our conscience is ââ¬Ëalwaysââ¬â¢ right despite it not necessarily entailing good ââ¬â is this really the kind of mindset we want when making ââ¬Ëethical decisionsââ¬â¢? If one is to take Humeââ¬â¢s view of appetital dominance, the human essence being the guidance of our nature, we can, to an extent, countermand this. One might argue that the conscience is just a constraint on our essential urges. A constraint on the collectiveââ¬â¢s blossoming; Sartre asserting that ââ¬Å"we must act out passion before we can feel itâ⬠27. Even today in such a complex, interlaced world there is a question over whether our primitive essence would beget greater happiness. Not at all am I suggesting that humans should revert to being primal, nor that happiness should be the human raceââ¬â¢s ultimate goal, but, in terms of making ââ¬Ëethical decisionsââ¬â¢, must one rely on the conscience? Indeed, there is a danger that reliance on appetites would encourage societal and individual regression. Hence, a viable alternative must be suggested. For me, this comes in the form of Social Darwinism (ââ¬Ësurvival of the fittestââ¬â¢); that mankind evolves by means of competition, ââ¬Å"the very essence of instinct is that itââ¬â¢s followed independently of reasonâ⬠28. Darwin appeared to prioritise appetites; using them as a means for societal progression. One might assert that this ideal comes closest to loosening the fetters of both individual conscience and societal restraint, whilst not jeopardising our future. In answering the question, the various examples presented in this essay ââ¬â of the conscience being dominant in its essence ââ¬â suggest to me that in any case the conscience deters our ââ¬Ëdecisionââ¬â¢-making. Indeed, if we feel by any means constrained we are unable to make pure, objective ââ¬Ëethical decisionsââ¬â¢, ergo, we should not be subservient to the conscience when making them. 1 Collins Dictionary & Thesaurus: Two books in one, 2004 2 Concise Oxford Dictionary: Tenth Edition, 1999 3 1 Thessalonians 5:23 4 Richard D. Patterson, The Third Day Motif, The Use Of Three In The Bible 5 The Internet Encyclopaedia of Philosophy 6 Joseph Butler. Class notes. 7 This is addressed further with the issue of guilt later on. 8 Plato, The Republic 9 Plato, Phaedrus 10 This is intended to mean the essence of God, rather than merely ââ¬Ëgod-likeââ¬â¢ attributes. 11 Popeââ¬â¢s Letter On Newman 12 David Hume 13 Sir Francis Bacon 14 Joseph Butler 15 Nineteen Eighty-Four, Part 2, Chapter 2 16 Nineteen Eighty-Four, Part 2, Chapter 2 17 Simon Soloveychik, Free Man 18 Spinozaââ¬â¢s Ethics 19 David Hume 20 John B. Watson 21 Sigmund Freud 22 Sigmund Freud 23 Fourth Lateran Council 24 Fyodor Dostoyevsky, Crime and Punishment, Chapter 19 25 Hamlet, Act 3 Scene 3, l. 40 26 Jewish commentary 27 Jean-Paul Sartre 28 Charles Darwin
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.